RIGHTS OF PEOPLE WITH DISABILITIES 

by Anita Silvers

San Francisco State University

(To be published in THE OXFORD BOOK OF PRACTICAL ETHICS, edited by Hugh LaFollette, Oxford University Press, 2001.) 1.The Disability Problem 1.1 Seeking The Right To Be In The World Writing two years after the passage of the 1964 Civil Rights Act, Jacobus tenBroek argued that " . . . nothing could be more essential to personality, social existence, economic opportunity ... than ,,, the legal right to be abroad in the land."(tenBroek 1966: 842) TenBroek held degrees from the law schools at Harvard and Berkeley, had taught at the University of Chicago's law school, and was a tenured U.C.-Berkeley professor when he wrote the classic law review article entitled "The Right To Be in the World". Despite his status as a nationally acclaimed legal scholar, tenBroek himself had no legal right to be abroad in the land. In virtue of his being blind, his claim to the right to be in the world was unrecognized in law and in life. TenBroek had no legal recourse when restaurants declined to serve him, or banks refused to let him deposit his money, or he was denied carriage on a train or plane for which he had purchased a regular ticket, simply because he was blind. Regardless of his competence and accomplishments, he expected to be held the responsible party if, in traversing the university campus, he fell into any open pit thoughtlessly left unguarded by a repair crew or was injured in a collision with a recklessly speeding campus-owned vehicle. Because he was disabled, tenBroek had to absorb harms against which nondisabled peers were protected. At the time when civil rights protections were specified in statute for other minorities and women, the disabled had been passed over. Although tenBroek could not know it, the next two decades would witness many failed attempts to extend existing civil rights statutes to safeguard disabled people. The reasons were both political and conceptual, with traditional civil rights groups sometimes joining the usual opponents of government regulation to block adding disability discrimination to the list of offenses against citizens' civil rights.(Burgdorf, 1991) Representatives of the groups protected under earlier legislation feared opening it to amendments protecting the disable might diffuse the focus of antidiscrimination enforcement. Moreover, some representatives of groups traditionally disadvantaged on the basis of race or sex simply could not conceive that people with disabilities were similarly mistreated (Burgdorf, 1991). They thought of the disabled as being naturally deficient rather than artificially limited by biased social practice. They thought of disabled people as definitively incompetent, even while complaining about stereotyping when this same ascription was applied to women and racial minorities. To make disability a category that activates a heightened legal shield against exclusion, it was objected, would alter the purpose of legal protection for civil rights by transforming the goal from protecting opportunity for socially exploited people to providing assistance for naturally unfit people (Burgdorf, 1991). TenBroek showed that standards of care, conduct, risk and liability for the disabled were inferior to those nondisabled people enjoyed.(tenBroek, 1966: 842) Such exclusions seemed to him inconsistent with the progressive policy President Johnson declared, and the Supreme Court affirmed, in supporting the Civil Rights Act, according to which denying equal access to public facilities to any group of citizens is a wrong and a burden on commerce. "According to the policy of integrationism, the disabled are not to be confined to their houses, asylums, and institutions -- threatened, if they emerge, with not only social sanctions but legal sanctions as well, in the form of legal barriers, disadvantages, and inadequate protections. ... Such confinement would in effect be a form of house arrest." (tenBroek, 1966: 848-849) 1.2 Historical Exclusion of People With Disabilities The system of removing people from the community because they are disabled took hold in the United States in the middle of the last century. Before 1820, disabled people stayed with their families or found places elsewhere in their immediate communities. During the next forty years, however, residential schools meant to train these individuals so that they could be more productive sprung up, supported by charitable donations and government funds. Up until the Civil War, these institutions focused on improving the skills and therefore the productivity of corporeally or cognitively impaired people, and on giving them access to the word of God, in order to return them to the community to earn their own livings. (Trent, 1994; Baynton, 1996, Carlson, 1998) After the Civil War, residential schools evolved into custodial facilities comparable to those that had existed for centuries in Europe. Several contributing factors promoted the change. Waves of immigrants arrived to provide labor, making it harder for disabled people to support themselves. As more jobs were factory-based, caring for an impaired family member interfered more and more with wage earning. So custodial institutions were enlarged to relieve private citizens of the burden of caring for the disabled.(Trent, 1994; Carlson, 1998). These "homes" then vigorously pursued the institutionalization of less impaired individuals who, once confined, spent their lifetimes being caregivers withoutremuneration for more seriously dysfunctional inmates. For instance, when a new young superintendent had inmates at the Iowa Home for Feeble-Minded Children assessed in the early 1950s, he found more than fifty with normal IQs higher than some of the employees. They had been institutionalized because families, physicians, or public officials found their anomalies disturbing. (One had been institutionalized for sixty years because of his peculiar eyerolling.) (Trent, 1994) For a century, the custodial system went unchallenged. But in the mid-twentieth century images of its inhumanities were widely circulated by the media to the public. Just after World War II, Life magazine's "Snakepit" story revealed the horrors of the treatment of patients in psychiatric institutions with images reminiscent of photographs of Nazi concentration camp survivors. PM, a progressive New York daily, ran pictures of the horrors of Letchworth, an asylum for cognitively impaired individuals. A quarter decade later, after the Civil Rights Act, the disgusting conditions of Letchworth persisted. Within a few months of being committed to the institution, all inmates contracted hepatitis because they were forced to live in each others' filth. Many similar exposes, illustrated with haunting images, appeared in printed or televised news throughout the second half of the twentieth century. It took another quarter century, however, for the courts to affirm that this custodial system could be discriminatory as well as inhumane. In Olmstead (1999), the U.S. Supreme Court was for the first time able to invoke an explicitly applicable federal civil rights statute --- the 1990 Americans With Disabilities Act (ADA) --- in deliberating on this matter. In the Findings that preface the ADA, the Congress stipulates that "historically, society has tended to isolate and segregate individuals with disabilities, and, despite some improvements, such forms of discrimination against individuals with disabilities continue to be a serious and pervasive social problem."(ADA, 1990) Further, the ADA defines as discriminatory the failure to integrate the dispersion of goods and services to disabled people into their distribution to the broader public. Providing different goods or segregated services is nondiscriminatory only if there is no other possible way to offer equally effective opportunity to a disabled individual. In Olmstead, the court declared that "... unjustified institutional isolation of persons with disabilities is a form of discrimination" and that recognition of the discriminatory potential of the custodial system " reflects two evident judgments." First, by confining individuals capable of living in the world to institutions and isolating them, the system perpetuates unwarranted assumptions about their capability and worthiness. Second, confinement deprives these individuals of family relations, social contacts, work options, economic independence, educational advancement, and cultural enrichment. If people with disabilities must relinquish participation in community life to receive services, but nondisabled people need not make similar sacrifices to receive equivalent services, the Court ruled, dissimilar treatment of a discriminatory nature exists. (Olmstead, 1999) Only recently has the statutory climate encouraged the courts to recognize that segregating the disabled is discriminatory and that people with disabilities have the same right as other people to be in the world. In the United States, even in an era of substantial commitment to furthering civil rights, it took 0;3 several decades to stimulate this process. Eventually, disability advocates abandoned efforts to integrate recognition of their rights into existing civil rights statutes. They turned instead to laws specifically addressed to the disabled, That law-making process began with the Architectural Barriers Act of 1968 to mandate access to the built public environment and reached full expression in the 1990 Americans with Disabilities Act. Even so, the bias of which tenBroek complained has yet to be dislodged from the justice system. To illustrate, a recent law review article revisited the tort law issues tenBroek addressed and concluded that the goal of integrating people with disabilities into society will remain a distant one because courts still do not comprehend what is entailed in the legal recognition of their right to live in the world. (Milani, 1999) Further, each year brings new political and legal action aimed at reducing their statutory protection. 1.3 The Conceptual Exclusion of People with Disabilities TenBroek believes our political and legal practice should evolve to recognize the right of disabled people to full and equal places in the world. This proposal poses some enormous challenges to everyday thinking. The conceptual problems are as vexatious in the United States as in nations which do not have civil rights traditions. Before we can fully embrace and apply the idea that disabled people are equal, we must eliminate bias from the ways we conceptualize and communicate about disability. The ways we currently think and talk about disability create barriers by making the integration of people with disabilities appear unimaginable, impossible, or undeserved. Our conceptualizations of disability lead us to speak or think as if being disabled were definitively bad. The source of the badness of disability commonly is thought to be its connection with physical, sensory, or cognitive impairments, those differences that mark the disabled as being other than species-typical. But what do we mean when we talk about impairment? By definition, an impairment may be an absence, deletion, omission, reduction or diminution. These states are anomalous in that they differ from what is typical, but anomalies are not necessarily harmful, disadvantageous or otherwise bad. However, an impairment may also be thought of as a weakness, inadequacy or loss. In conceptualizing disability, we too easily slide down a slippery slope from attributions of anomalies to verdicts of badness. To characterize an anomaly as a weakness or loss improperly closes by definition what should be an open empirical process of particularized valuing, for whether a particular physical or cognitive difference is unfavorable should 13 be an open question. Thus, the commonplace elision of the first meaning of "impairment" with the second, so that the negative value of disability is assumed rather than investigated, is a source of bias. Because listening, seeing, walking, and other such performances are commonplace in most people's daily lives, we imagine that the sheer exercise of the faculties that support them necessarily gratifies us. From this assumption, we stray to the views that sight, hearing, and mobility are good in themselves, and, consequently, their absence constitutes a net loss of intrinsically valuable experience and a reduction of the quality of life. In this regard, it is argued that not being able to hear music or look at paintings is supposed to be intrinsical ly bad. Yet no one questions the quality of life of the many nondisabled people who could enjoy these pleasures but pass them up. It seems biased to say foregoing these pleasures is deleteri ous to those who cannot experience them but indifferent to those who can but don't experience them. There are other common ways of speaking that make it difficult for most people to talk about or think of a disability as anything but bad. To illustrate, genetic counselors call the probability that a baby will have a disability a "risk". This rhetorical convention places prospective parents on the defensive if they do not display reservations about having such a child. They are expected to justify continuing "risky" pregnancies that may result in children with disabilities, but the discourse does not equally require them to defend pregnancies with no such prognosis. (Silvers, 1998b) In other words, the discourse exerts conceptual pressure by putting the parents on the defensive if they do not exclude the option of living with (a child with a) disability. A series of exchanges between philosophers Bryan Magee and Martin Milligan - published under the title On Blindness (Magee and Milligan, 1995) - further illustrates the conceptual burden borne by whoever remains neutral about disability or questions the assumption that it is bad. Magee wanted to discover whether someone like Milligan, blind nearly from birth and with no memory of seeing, can understand what visual language means and what is conveyed by other people's reports of visual experience. Magee hypothesizes that blindness is not just a sensory impairment, but a significant epistemic deficit as well. Sight is useful, Milligan acknowledges. Nevertheless, he demonstrates that, despite his impairment, he can understand what is involved in, and is the product of, visual judgment: "You seem to have found my claims that born-blind people can understand, at the very least, a major part of the meaning of visual terms, and that many sighted people grossly exaggerate the importance of sight, somewhat exasperating in their presumption. (B)ecause the sense of which they make overwhelmingly the greatest use is sight, sighted people just cannot imagine how blind people can manage without it." (Magee and Milligan, 1995: 42 - 43). Magee, though, insists that whoever considers blindness a difference rather than a handicap is "refusing to face the reality of his situation" (p. 99). He advances his case not through argument but by using rhetorical conventions that privilege the sighted over the blind. For him, people with disabilities must bear the burden of proving they are not incompetent. Magee never meets Milligan's argument that blind people enjoy a more comprehensive standpoint on the subject than sighted people: "(W)hereas most sighted people will have known few if any blind people, and (if any) will often not have known them very well, born-blind people will usually have known a lot of other blind people, including blind people who have had sight, and also a lot of sighted people, and will have known some of both groups very well. (B)lind people are apt to know a good deal more about sight and sighted people than the latter can know about blindness and blind people." (Magee and Milligan, 1995: 49) Milligan explains that erroneous conceptions of blind people's competence occur because sighted people, who are in the majority, have come to rely on vision instead of practicing the full range of human skills: "... because sight is in modern conditions so much more efficient than the other senses, sighted people have got into the habit of disregarding a lot of the information the other senses provide, or can provide."(Magee and Milligan, 1995: 44-45) Of course, blindness does not inherently enhance hearing, nor deafness sight, any more than paraplegia inherently builds up the shoulders and arms. What deafness does do, however, is invite increased attentiveness to effective looking, as blindness does to proficient listening. Looking or listening with greater skill increases the value realized by these perceptual modes. So people with certain kinds of sensory impairments may realize more epistemic value than is typical for members of the human species, in that they are informed by sensory data nondisabled people disregard. Thus, even if an impairment occasions a specific disadvantage, we should not assume it results in a net loss of capability or of quality of life The problem, then, is that Magee assumes that species typical behavior constitutes the appropriate standard for competence. But this kind of "normalizing" is a bias that violates Hume's prohibition against conflating "ought" with "is", that is, against unreflectively equating what is typical with what is desirable. As Alexander Rosenberg points out, modern biology suggests that there is no "base-line repertoire of abilities common to normal agents" that is adaptive for the organism.(Rosenberg, 1986: 5) In imposing such a groundless standard, the dialogue inflicts a grave inequity. The heaviness of the burden of proof imposed on those who, like Milligan, approach being disabled nonjudgmentally is patently unfair in comparison to the light burden of proof placed on those who, like Magee, normalize by assuming without proving that being deaf or blind or crippled is intrinsically bad. This bias is not confined to philosophical dialogue. It pervades many rhetorical domains. Often, specific protections and remedies must be legislated to relieve disabled people from such bias. For example, tenBroek demonstrated that common law tort theory is biased against blind people when they are required to adhere to an exceptionally high standard of care in respect to avoiding injury, so much so that they can be convicted of contributory negligence simply by being in a location where they are endangered by other people's thoughtlessness. To flush out this deeply embedded bias, the National Foundation of the Blind, over which tenBroek presided, lobbied for "white cane laws". These state statutues decree that blind (and deaf) pedestrians have the rights and privileges of other pedestrians, including the right to go abroad in the land without signaling their blindness or relying on guides. Thus these statutes abrogate the common law rule imposing an unduly high standard of precaution on disabled people. Rectifying such bias through legislation protects against deviations from species typicality being prsumptively designated as bad and thereby being assumed to underwrite unfavorable treatment. It does not preclude acknowledging that seeing well, hearing well, and moving well are valuable. Nor does such assurance ignore the fact that impairment often is experienced as a loss by those who become disabled, especially later in life. Impairment that affects a particular mode of performance may preclude exercise of some of a person's special talents or enjoyment of some of her personal pleasures. Eliminating such accustomed performance is likely to disrupt the core of how one lives one's life, just as losing any other familiar lifeplan component, aloved child or spouse, an important opportunity or possession, a respected community role, would do. These considerations reveal thatbadness lies in the dislocation of familiar patterns, which may but need not be occasioned by disability, rather than in disability itself. (Fuhrer, 2000: 484) 1.3.1 Does Disability Diminish Quality of Life? The onset of disability can disturb the flow of individuals' lives. Such persons' distress understandably is magnified when they are subjected to biased conceptualizations that place them on the defensive, when their right to be in the world is ignored or denied, and when they must battle for recognition of their competence. They also are stressed by policies shaped by the assumption that to have a disability makes a person's life inherently less valuable. For instance, in 1927, the U.S. Supreme Court declared that the state has a legitimate interest in preventing the births of disabled people whose existence detracts from the welfare of the community (Buck v. Bell, 1927). As late the 1930s, more than half the states in this country had laws on the books encouraging sterilization of people with disabilities, usually those with developmental disabilities, but also those blind or deaf (regardless of whether their conditions were inherited or accidental). California's eugenic sterilization law may have inspired the Nazi program of euthanizing members of these same groups.(Kevles, 1998: 3) In Western Europe, eugenic practices existed well past the half century mark. Recently, the world has learned that programs of sterilizing people designated as disabled accompanied the post-World War II expansion of generous social service policies in Scandinavia and the Netherlands. (Silvers et. al, 1998). These programs, Kevles reports, were predicated on the proposition that disabled people burdened the community by proliferating at a rate that placed great pressure on social resources and stability. (Kevles, 1998: 3) In health care practice, suggests bioethicist Leon Kass, a similar attitude propels the assumption that the lives of people with disabilities makes them burdensome to themselves.(Kass, 1983: 400) But it is illegitimate to assume that disability is necessarily burdensome. Despite the depleted opportunities they are offered, many disabled people equal or excede the typical social contributions of nondisabled individuals. And though impairments may preclude some activities, such limitations need not have a deleterious impact on people's well-being. Not every limitation is a loss - and certainly not an intolerable loss. We know, for instance, that the absence of limitations can also lead to suffering. We may well be better off if we were be focused on a few fulfilling options than to be torn with indecision by many glittering ones. It is more important to learn to overcome disadvantageous circumstance when faced with limited, less than desirable, options. Because one has only one life to plan, the ultimate difference between having begun with a single, several, or many equally satisfying life plan opportunities may be negligible. It thus is problematic to identify disability with diminished worth of life. In fact, individuals who are experienced in living with a disability very often give a much higher rating to the quality of life disabled people can achieve than the nondisabled do (Murray 1996). The difference that a person's standpoint makes in how a health condition is experienced foregrounds an important issue about conceptual bias. "(M)any of the outcome measures (used in health services research) reflect the hegemony of providers' and payers' values," and only equivocally those of disabled people.(Fuhrer, 2000: 487) Constructing a univocal standpoint usually means defining away the perspectives of disabled people so that these have no weight within the assessmen system. "These models do not lend themselves to providing a holisti portrayal of people's living with a disability." (Fuhrer, 2000: 483) There are further problems with the way disability is assessed in health care service allocation. Attempting to calibrate his disability-adjusted life year(DALY) scale, Murray reports that, if forced to choose between extending the life of a larger number of blind people than seeing people, most nondisabled people choose to benefit the larger group, suggesting that they assign the same value to each life whether the individual is disabled or not. However, the same subjects think it more important to restore sight to a blind person than to extend a nondisabled person's life by a year. Murray interprets these results as incoherent, and therefore as of no relevance to the appropriateness of his scale. He thinks his respondents inconsistently hold both that disabled people's lives are identically valuable to nondisabled people's, but also that eliminating a disability makes a person's life more valuable than it was with the disability.(Murray, 1996: 36) As is characteristic in the health care service discourse, this interpretation fails to distinguish between the burden of disability and the burden of life with disability. It is not inconsistent to think that being blind is a burden, an obstacle one must constantly work around, but that being alive while blind is not a burden, regardless of the challenges associated with being blind. Analogously, being poor usually is a burden but this does not entail that it is better not to live at all than to live with poverty. Murray reminds us that the limitation associated with an impairment may differ depending on environment. The same impairment may be more or less disabling in an advanced technological society than in a simple rural one. It is well known that mild mental retardation does not disable women in environments in which a woman's role is restricted to cleaning, cooking, and bearing children. It would be inequitable to allocate resources to rich societies to prevent a type of impairment but not to poor ones, Murray believes, even though "in many cases (programs) to avert impairment could exacerbate inequalities" by eliminating disabled people from reproductive roles. (Murray, 1996: 33). Surely, however, there is nothing inequitable in acknowledging that an impairment is no burden at all where it is not experienced as one. Indeed, it is more inequitable to treat people as dysfunctional when they actually are not than to refrain from intervening where intervention harms them. A medical intervention is unlikely to be experienced as beneficial by individuals who were not dysfunctional prior to it and are no more functional, relative to their environment, as a result of it. To illustrate, adults with congenitally anomalous limbs, such as those occasioned by the pre-natal presence of thalidomide, often believe themselves to have been injured as children by being fitted with dysfunctional artificial arms and forbidden to develop the much more functional method of manipulating objects with their feet.(Baughn et. al., 2000) Undergoing a medical intervention almost always costs the patient some pain and risk. As long as the patient is competent, commensurability demands that the benefit offsetting the patient's cost be in terms of the patient's own experience of good. But this perspective usually has been disregarded in favor of a medical point of view that gives normality priority over functionality.(Fuhrer, 2000: 482) From the medical perspective, access to the world is achieved by functioning in a species-typical way. So on this view, claims to equality either are predicated on the claimants' species-typical functioning, or else are directed toward enabling the claimants to function at typical levels and in common ways. 2. Solving the Disability Problem 2.1 Models of Disability 2.1.1 The Medical Model In our era, a medical model of disability has pervaded political, legal and other thought as thoroughly as it has dominated health care services policymaking. This model has important implications for the assignment of rights. On it, people are disabled when they are biologically anomalous - when they are less functionally proficient than is typical for most humans. Norman Daniels puts it this way: "The basic idea is that ... diseases (I here include deformities and disabilities that result from trauma) are deviations from the natural functional organization of a typical member of a species" (Daniels, 1987: 302). The job of medicine then is to maintain or restore species-typical functioning. This medical model is applied to defeat claims that disabled people have rights to equitable access to the opportunities of the world. It is not reasonable to expect such access in the absence of species-typical functioning, Daniels claims: "Life plans we are otherwise suited for and have a reasonable expectation of finding satisfying or happiness-producing are rendered unreasonable by impairments of normal functioning ... (I)f people have a higher-order interest in preserving ... opportunity ..., then they will have a pressing interest in maintaining normal species functioning by establishing institutions - such as health care systems - that do just that"(Daniels, 1987: 302). What could be a more natural, and modest, expectation than the prospect of individuals desiring to function as their species typically does? Broad-based public support for policies that reduce whatever biological anomalies or singularities hinder adherence to the species-typical functional standard seems natural. As deTocqueville remarked, the inclination to create fair opportunity by leveling the players rather than the playing field is a strong force in egalitarian societies. There is, nevertheless, an abiding question about the propriety of making homogeneity the price of opportunity. Normalizing policies can worsen the position, or otherwise oppress, the very individuals they purport to improve by decreeing that inequality of opportunity is the unavoidable consequence of not functioning in the normal, typical or customary way. Daniels supposes that an objective biological principle warrants restoring impaired individuals so that they function typically for the species (Daniels, 1987: 303). However, Ron Amundson challenges Daniel's view. According to him the idea of normal function has no foundation in objective biological fact because very large amounts of heritable variation occur in natural species.(Amundson, 2000a: 36) In modern biology dogmas about determinate species design have given way to appreciation of rich ranges of variation. No nature-based justification underwrites making social justice conditional upon normality (or upon species- typicality, which often is confused with normality). That there are average, common or typical modes and levels of human performances does not make these the normal or natural modes and levels for humankind (Sober, 1980). Biology tends to eliminate dysfunctional individuals, not to repair them, 2.1.2 The Social Model The medical model understands the reduction of opportunity occasioned by disability in terms of the disabled's personal deficits, but people with disabilities often interpret their situation differently. They understand their limitations in terms of social rather than personal deficits. This social model of disability transforms the notion of "handicapping condition" from a biological state which disadvantages unfortunate individu als to a state of society which disadvantages an oppressed minority. The social model attributes the dysfunction experienced by people with disabilities primarily to hostile social arrange ments. For instance, Richard Hull examines the condition of disabled people in Britain. Like other nations, social arrangements in Britain are such that people with disabilities incur significant extra cost to meet the conditions for social participation. Yet, disability welfare payments are insufficient to meet this cost, and institutional discrimination against disabled people is prevalent throughout the labor market.(Hull, 1998: 201-202) Hull observes: "Contrary to the conventional view, ... functional limitation does not always secure or guarantee disadvantage. ,,, society can be equally to blame, or more to blame, in many cases." (Hull, 1998: 203) On this social view of disability, socially constructed barriers are the primary disadvantage faced by people who do not function in species-typical ways. These obstructions range from discriminatory practices such as disability-based denial of employment through thoughtlessly inaccessible design such as the installation of steps rather than ramps. Sometimes the absence of adequate support services and health care benefits also is construed as a barrier to the effective functioning of people with certain kinds of impairments.(Silvers et. al., 1998) From this perspective, the preeminent strategy of the medical model - namely, altering biologically anomalous people to make them species-typical or normal - unfairly disparages personal traits central to the identity of individuals with disabilities. Further, by placing a premium on medically altering them so as to bring their modes of functioning into better conformity with species-typical functioning, this medicalized approach to disability can be coercive and can expose the disabled to risky or ineffective medical interventions. Consequently, from this viewpoint, reforming social arrangements to achieve equitable opportunity and accessibility is the best route to reducing dysfunction in biologically anomalous people. The social model thus entails that the solution to the "disability problem" lies in fully realizing disabled people's right to be in the world. There are two competing schools of philosophical thought about this right. The first rests firmly on the social model by arguing that "injustices may be better remedied by changing social norms and the structure of public goods than by redistributing resources."(Anderson, 1999: 336) On this first view, enabling disabled people to be in the world is grounded in the collective good of achieving a democratically equitable social order based on principles that express respect for everyone. This approach emphasizes participatory rights that give disabled people claims to inclusion in social practice and to revision of such practice if needed for access. The second straddles the medical and social models by revising the distribution of private goods to improve disabled individuals' personal capacity to cope with existing social norms. On this second view, disabled people's right to be in the world is grounded in the individual good of achieving personal satisfaction based on principles that promote well-being for everyone. This later approach claims the disabled are due compensatory rights to repair their deficits, relieve their needs, or mitigate the consequences of their losses. 2.2 Disability Rights 2.2.1. Disability Rights as Participatory Rights Philosophers like Elizabeth Anderson (Anderson, 1999), Anita Silvers(Silvers, 1995, 1997, Silvers et. al.,1998) and Iris Marion Young (Young, 1990) all take justice to be about interpersonal respect and inclusive social participation. They argue that to treat disabled people equally requires reshaping the practices that exclude them. From a disability perspective, physical or cognitive limitations are not absences of talent, but instead are constraints upon the functional modes through which talents are exercised. Social arrangements that offer equivalent prospects of success to people of similar talent and ambition provide fair equality of opportunity. Fair equality of opportunity requires that people with similar talents should enjoy equitable access to the necessary social conditions for realizing their talents, regardless of whether their functional modes are normal or anomalous. On this kind of view, equality is a social relationship which is free of exclusion, coercion, and oppression. Anderson and Silvers follow Iris Marion Young in identifying inegalitarianism with claims about the necessary dominance by some social groups of others, usually on the ground that the former have superior intrinsic worth while the latter are incompetent or otherwise intrinsically inferior.(Silvers, 1995, passim; Anderson, 1999: 311-312) To secure equality, the social patterns in which people interact, and through which personal goods are actualized and interchanged, must express respect for everyone alike, whether fortunate or unfortunate, judicious or reckless, through mutual, reciprocal consultation and action. (Anderson, 1999: 313) Of course, functioning as a social being requires functioning as a human being, which involves effective access to the means of sustaining one's biological existence and agency. It also requires effective access to the means of being productive, of developing talents, and of forming relationships in civil society. (Anderson, 1999: 318) Therefore, regardless of whether one is typically or anomalously circumstanced, everyone equally has a right to social arrangements that provide the enabling conditions for these fundamental capabilities. (Anderson, 1999: 331) In this way, democratic equality matches remedy to injus tice. If, as tenBroek describes, the fundamental injustice done to the disabled is to exclude them from the world, the remedy lies in assigning them the direct right to the means of inclu sion, not the circuitous right to be compensated for exclusion by gaining satisfaction in some alternative way. (Anderson, 1999: 334). In this spirit, Anita Silvers proposes a test for the justice of specific social practices to see whether their exclusionary aspects grow out of the dominance of nondisabled people's convenience and tastes. "Historically counterfactualizing" is a conceptual test which involves asking whether a practice would be the same if the disabled individuals it marginalizes were the majority, not a powerless minority, of people. Its purpose is to free our imaginations from the constricting routine of institutionalized behaviors so that we are not misled into assuming that the familiarity of a practice entails signals its biological or economic necessity. (Silvers, 1995, 1998, 2000, Silvers et. al. 1998) Historical counterfactualizing indicates whether, by broadening assumptions about the variety of modes in which individuals achieve function, we can and should redesign a practice so that anomalous individuals can partake of the collective good it secures. For instance, the practice of privileging visual over aural and tactile media for storing data disregards the functional modes in which blind and dyslexic individuals retrieve information. This exclusionary practice is of no moment to the majority of sighted users. If, however, individuals for whom looking at texts is dysfunctional were the majority, the relative ease of storing and conveying information in a variety of media would make offering information in alternative formats the rule rather than the exception, (Silvers, 2000) Historical counterfactualizing helps us to identify disadvantage that is the arbitrary artifact of social arrangements controlled by the standard of normality. It facilitates distinguishing arrangements that do no more than conform to the dominant group's tastes and preferences from arrangements that have more to recommend them. Tastes and preferences are transitory. The practices they elicit need not be perpetual. Exclusionary practices dominate, Silvers believes, because most often they are comfortable for the majority and disadvantage only a minority of people. Although the majority may be discomforted by the evolution familiar but restrictive practices must go through to become more inclusive, their social participation is not threatened by such change. Thus, on balance, such social reform is less burden some for members of the majority than enduring exclusion is for members of the minority. While some alterations of practice to repair disadvantages suffered by the disabled can be justified as countering arbitrary cultural affinities for normality, historical counterfactualization also helps identify customary components of disability policy that do not have such a warrant. To illustrate, the disabled have been disadvantaged in gaining access to the workplace. So it sometimes is thought that equity calls for providing compensatory income for them, as this is what they themselves would secure were they to command sufficient political influence. Yet there is no reason to think that, were the disabled the majority instead of the minority, they could command compensatory income. For were most people disabled, it would surely be very difficult for the able-bodied minority to care for and sustain so many people with disabilities. So were the nondisabled in the minority, it is less rather than more likely that they could guarantee to provide subsistence for the disabled. Counterfactualizing thus reveals nothing arbitrary nor inequitable if society does not supply such care. Indeed, counterfactualizing indicates a significant problem with the strategy of utilizing compensatory income to offset the social disadvantage disability occasions. For the feasibility of doing so wanes with increases in the population of people who are excluded from the workplace because of their disabilities. This result suggests that reducing exclusion is preferable to compensating for it. (Silvers, 1995. Silvers et. al., 1998) 2.2.2 Negative and Positive Disability Rights This debate fits nicely into the larger philosophical debates about positive and negative rights. For philosophers who propose reshaping social practice to permit disabled people to fully participate in society, ensuring them the same liberatory rights that others enjoy is preferable to granting them special compensatory rights. Although such emancipation from social restriction usually is associated with the exercise of negative rights, it may be misleading to impose the traditional template of positive and negative rights on our consideration of disability rights. Negative rights limit the ways in which the activities of rights bearers may be obstructed; the state has a duty to ensure that the exercise of these rights is not restricted and consequently must ensure that rights bearers are free of the prohibited constraints. Positive rights are entitlements to benefits the state has a duty to provide to rights bearers. (Gewirth, 1992) Ensuring the successful exercise of either kind of right has its costs: typically, allocation mechanisms, such as the social security system, must be available to support positive rights bearers, while enforcement mechanisms, such as the judicial system, must be available to protect negative rights bearers. Discrimination curtails liberty by corrupting the routes of access to productivity and fulfillment. Claimants to protection against discrimination traditionally call on the resources of the state to extirpate harms that arise when the bigotry or arbitrariness of public and proprietary entities blocks this access for certain kinds of people. Their claims are to relatively "thick" rights which command positive action to open the routes to accomplishment.(Silvers, 2000) There is neither agreement nor clarity regarding the point at which a thick negative right transforms into a thin positive right. Responses to discrimination sometimes appear to proffer special preferences similar to the entitlements associated with positive rights. For instance, U.S. disability discrimination law requires employers and program operators to make reasonable accommodations to give disabled people meaningful access to productive, fulfilling social participation. Regulations that direct the installation of toilet stalls wide enough for wheelchairs in office buildings, or the toleration of guide dogs in restaurants and airplanes, may appear to entitle disabled individuals to extra cost and exertion on other people's part, rather than merely to protect their liberties. Thus, claims to such accommodations may appear to exercise positive rather than negative rights. (Illingworth and Parmet, 2000) From a disability perspective, however, these regulations protect disabled people's liberty to access toilets, restaurants and planes. For to make being stripped of one's mobility device (because toilet stall doorways are very narrow, for example) or one's visual alerting system (because guide dogs are banned from a restaurant or plane, for example) the condition of entering a facility is as much a curtailment of one's liberty as to make cutting off a person's legs or poking out his eyes the price of entry would be. This last observation illuminates one respect in which reshaping social practice resembles implementation of a negative, rather than a positive, right. While positive rights are entitlements assigned to some among us, negative rights are shields for all citizens alike. The characteristic defense of a claim to a positive right involves differentiating those said to be deserving of it from other individuals. In contrast, the characteristic defense of a claim to a negative right involves assimilating those who lack a liberty to other individuals who already enjoy it. When disabled people pursue recognition of their right to be in the world, they seek the same freedoms of access as are afforded without question to other citizens. For to alter practice so that civic and commercial facilities can be utilized by those who substitute mechanical devices or animal aides for legs and arms, or eyes or ears, is simply to give disabled people the same freedoms of social participation as other people enjoy. Thus, when disability rights are claims for participation, they appear to fall within the negative rights tradition. For people who need undergo no struggle in order to be in the world, being asked to make an effort to accommodate people with disabilities may be misperceived as privileging this minority and so may be received with resentment. To make clear that such accommodation only offers disabled people freedoms others enjoy, it is advisable, as Iris Marion Young points out, to adopt public and commercial policies aimed at fostering inclusion by accommodating the differences of all citizens, not just those certified as falling into the disability category. For instance, nondisabled and disable workers alike should challenge employers to create more individualized, accommodating and humane workplaces.(Young, 2000) 2.2.3. Disability Rights as Compensatory Rights Nevertheless, philosophers who take justice to be mainly concerned with the fair allocation of resources often think that access to social opportunity is a peripheral issue when it comes to the disabled. They assert that disabled people characteristically need more than the usual resources. This to them is the main source of the problem of disability. Adherents of the view that equalizing must offer more than opportunity urge that something more than leveling the playing field must be done. Individuals also must be made capable of leaving the starting gate, even if doing so involves an unevenness in how goods and services are allocated. In general, for disabled people to flourish, extra resources are needed to remedy the results of their limitations. Disability thus poses a philosophical challenge, that of determining whether the disabled can receive greater portions of goods than other people do without being unfairly privileged by the allocation scheme. Richard Arneson (Arneson, 2000), Jerome Bickenbach (Bickenbach, 1993, 2000), Dan Brock (Brock, 1995, 2000), Allen Buchanan (Buchanan, 1995, 1996), Ronald Dworkin (Dworkin, 1994), Amartya Sen (Sen, 1980, 1992, 1993) and David Wasserman (Silvers et. al., 1998) are among the well-known contributors to the literature on this subject. Because natural differences, including impairments, affect well-being, Sen urges taking them into account in formulating just distributive arrangements. Sen believes justice requires allocating more resources to individuals who require them to enjoy basic capabilities. It is, for instance, merely just, rather than privileging, to provide more resources to people who need to purchase wheelchairs in order to mobilize than to people who can mobilize by walking. Brock thinks that some of the differences caused by impairments irremediably decrease well-being and therefore holds that resource allocation to people with these differences may be neither cost-effective nor otherwise beneficial. In a more nuanced view, Wasserman points out that any adequate view requires constructing a metric of well-being that respects the multiplicity of ways in which people can live well. An adequate view must also convincingly determine how much inequality in the distribution of well-being on this metric can be tolerated before differences in allocations become unjust. Arneson argues that "what we owe to one another by way of social justice requirements goes beyond ,,, nondiscrimination." He believes that "the provisions of the Americans with Disabilities Act ... cannot be fully justified by appeal even to the most plausible versions of the nondiscrimination ideal." (Arneson, 2000: 18) For Arneson, the preeminent ethical question in regard to disability is what we owe to people whose competence is so low as to compromise their wellbeing regardless of the excellence of their access to opportunity. Moral value is maximized by making gains in the expected wellbeing of individuals disadvantaged through no fault of their own. By increasing such individuals' material resources, we sometimes can reconfigure the circumstances that determine their lifetime allotment of wellbeing. So we are obligated to strive for satisfying outcomes for all deserving people alike, regardless of their differences of merit or talent. Such social intervention promotes a fairer distribution of wellbeing than could be accomplished by relying on individuals' good or ill luck in making good use of their access to opportunity. Undoubtedly, compensatory resources for goods and services conducive to wellbeing would benefit many people with disabilities. Nevertheless, Anderson criticizes Arneson for grounding justice for disabled people in considerations of the incompetence and consequent neediness of this class. Another problem is that Arneson particularizes allocation decisions by stating the criteria deserving beneficiaries must meet: blamelessness for their deficits and capacity to capitalize on allocated resources by achieving enhanced welfare. Individualized judgments are required to determine whether a particular disabled person meets these criteria and thus is qualified to exercise disability rights. Answering Anderson, Arneson likely would respond that we mainly should be concerned about improving the welfare of incompetent or unlucky disabled individuals rather than with improving the status of the disabled as a class. In sum, Arneson criticizes Anderson (and Silvers) for an account on which justice invites us to treat very differently disabled people homogeneously by giving less weight to the particulars of promoting deserving individuals' well-being than to avoiding actions that might stigmatize the class. On the other hand, Anderson criticizes luck egalitarians like Arneson for an account on which justice invites us to treat similarly disabled people differently, depending on the extent to which they are afflicted with personal problems. Is it appropriate merely to level the social playing field in ways that afford fair access to disabled people as a group? Or is it unrealistic, and thereby unfair, to expect these individuals to take the field at all, let alone succeed on it? Anderson and Arneson answer these questions in different ways because they have very different ideas about what is owed to people in virtue of being disabled. Anderson seems to construe basic disability rights as group rights. On this approach, disabled people have a collective right to a society in which the existence of their type of person is acknowledged, and where the differences that signify their group membership command respect. For example, in a society where there is respectful acknowledgment that some people do not hear, deaf people can expect information conveyed aurally also to be offered in a visual mode. Similarly, where practice is influenced by both the proposition that some people cannot see and the principle that their access to information is as important as anyone else's, blind people have a claim to aural or tactile versions of information that conventionally is presented visually. In addition to being grouped according to their impairments, all disabled people belong to the more comprehensive collection of individuals whose corporeal or cognitive anomalies result in some degree of non-species-typical performance. Together, they have a broad collective right to a society in which practices generally are inclusive of both species-typical and species-anomalous individuals. Within such a society, they may have derivative individual rights to enforcement or compensation as remedies for exclusion they suffer because they are disabled. Of course, even if a practice is as accessible as good will and good technology can make it, some disabled people will not engage in it successfully. But on this view, no one is owed success in virtue of being disabled (although there may be other grounds on which disabled and nondisabled individuals alike are owed basic components of wellbeing). In contrast, Arneson construes basic disability rights as individual rights. On this approach, disabled people have individual claims to a society in which each enjoys entitlements in virtue of having qualified for membership in the group of the deserving disabled. Where there is sufficient societal concern for people whose competence is compromised by disability, deaf people and blind people can, for example, expect resources to compensate for the loss of welfare occasioned by limited access to information, at least to the extent that these resources will elevate their wellbeing. Further, within such a society, disabled beneficiaries may have a derivative collective right to practices that make the allocation of resources effective. For example, to help make allocations of rehabilitative services to disabled individuals effective in securing the benefits of employment, disabled people may be assigned a derivative collective right to accessible public transportation to get to the workplace. However, unlike the former approach, where everyone is owed inclusion for its own sake, on this view no disabled individual is owed inclusion unless it is the most effective route to enhancement of her welfare. 2.3. Disability Rights and Disability Policy The positions represented by Anderson and Arneson lay out disability rights very differently, not only in respect to whether they are individual or collective, but also as to the fundamental values to be sought and achieved by exercising them. Their difference turns in part on a disparity in their conceptions of the connection between social participation and individual flourishing. The issue is whether the successful exercise of participatory rights in itself secures intrinsic value, or whether social participation is a mere instrument, one among other possibly effective approaches, for attaining intrinsically valuable results, namely, the increased welfare which is pursued through the exercise of compensatory rights. Philosophers who take the preeminent kind of disability right to be participatory suppose that individuals cannot flourish absent their joining with other humans in some sorts of collective activities. Thus, for them, participation is inherently valuable, and practices should be shaped to facilitate interaction between different kinds of people. A social environment that facilitates their connectedness is important for disabled and nondisabled individuals alike. Individuals' basic needs are to be assessed in terms of cultivating the capabilities they must have to maintain their social connections. Distributing resources to satisfy these individual needs secures instrumental value only. Allocation schemes that segregate or otherwise isolate their disabled recipients are counterproductive on this view. On the other hand, those who construe the preeminent kind of disability right to be compensatory suppose that participation in community activities contributes to, but is not necessary for, every human's wellbeing. To base disability rights on the value of social inclusion, they say, is to deny rights to very severely disabled people for whom access to participatory activities either is beside the point or not possible to achieve. Yet these are the individuals who, in virtue of the profundity of their disabilities, should be most able to have their claims on others acknowledged. Disability rights should be meaningful for the most disabled and responsive to their individualized situations. Therefore, allocating resources to satisfy these individual needs secures intrinsic value. Jonathan Wolff (Wolff, 2000) crafts a position that integrates the fair access and fair allocation approaches. Drawing on the work of Ronald Dworkin to propose how a society of equals should treat the disabled, Wolff identifies three acceptable responses: medical interventions remedying impairments that occasion disability, resource allocations compensating for disadvantages associated with disability, and social practice alterations nullifying disadvantages imposed on disability. The objective is to help each disabled individual find a place in the world. Regardless of which strategies we emphasize, Wolff reminds us, we must decide what amount of effort and resources to expend on doing so. Following Dworkin, he recommends imagining people behind a veil of ignorance, aware of the disadvantages of disability, its general prevalence, and the costs of remedial strategies, but unaware of their own disability status. We should consider how well, in what ways, and at what cost people who don't know whether they are or will be disabled would insure themselves against suffering exclusion should they become so. Tax revenues generated on this basis would be assigned to a government agency charged with pursuing the most effective combination of strategies - medical repairs, compensatory allocations and services, or reform of exclusionary social practices - both for individuals and for the general public. Wolff's solution reflects the current state of disability policy in many nations. Medical research and resources, funded by various public or private schemes, are applied to reduce the numbers of the disabled. Criteria of deservingness are applied to those who cannot be cured to determine the kind and amount of material resources and social services each should receive. More recently, attention has turned to requiring that environments be more accommodating to people with various kinds of biological anomalies. In some nations these strategies all are pursued by a single agency charged with addressing the disability problem. In others, different branches of government execute different aspects of disability policy. Regardless of how disability policy is administered, these components do not always co-exist compatibly. There are deep conceptual tensions between viewing the disability problem as primarily caused by discrimination and therefore as suscepti ble to a civil rights solution, and viewing it as primarily a social safety net issue and therefore as susceptible to a need- based benefits solution. How we credit what disabled people claim society owes them is influenced by whether the claim is framed as liberatory - that is, as a claim to opportunity all citizens should be positioned to enjoy - or as allocatory - that is, as a claim to assistance some citizens should be positioned to receive. In the United States, disability entitlement programs that are partially or fully need-based predated the application of the civil rights paradigm to disability discrimination. During the quarter-century that followed the Civil Rights Act of which Jacobus tenBroek had such high hopes, few provisions to relieve people with disabilities of their exclusion from social participation were integrated into comprehensive legislation aimed at safeguarding minorities generally. (The Fair Housing Amendments Act of 1988 is a notable exception.) Instead, their protection against discrimination was fashioned mainly by enacting or amending statutes pertaining solely or principally to the disabled. Important laws of this kind included the Rehabilitation Act, the Education for All Handicapped Children Act (now the Individuals with Disabilities Education Act), and the Developmental Disabilities Assistance and Bill of Rights Act. Having waited in vain for nearly a decade to draw the disabled under the shield of the 1964 Civil Rights Act, disability leaders eventually introduced a nondiscrimination provision into federal statute by amending the Rehabilitation Act. Sections 503 and 504 of the Rehabilitation Act prohibit denying individuals participation in federally funded programs or activities in virtue of their handicaps, but enforcement mechanisms was lodged mainly in funding agencies' complaint reviews. Eventually, the idea of achieving civil rights protection through a new federal statute specifically aimed at forbidding discrimination based on disability was adopted, and the Americans With Disabilities Act(ADA) became law in 1990. During the two decades between the amended Rehabilitation Act and the implementation of the ADA, the statutory conceptualization of disability discrimination seemed unproblematic. In the many investigations and rare litigations pursued under the Rehabilitation Act, actions centered mainly on whether complainants had been subjected to unwarranted exclusion. Disputes most often were over whether there were unburdensome ways in which disabled complainants could be given access to the benefits federally funded programs bestowed on nondisabled people. Complainants typically were people who suffered from diminished prospects for employment because of some limitation of body or mind. Thus such persons already met the criteria for services under the Rehabilitation Act. The relief they sought typically was pertinent to the core purpose of that legislation, for it commonly was an action or accommodation to gain or maintain (suitability for) employment. In the context of the Rehabilitation Act, reasonably accommodating to a person's disability generally is thought of as responding to the person's special needs. Consistent with the nature of the Rehabilitation Act as an entitlement to benefits statute, concerns that increasing the welfare of disabled complainants decreases other people's welfare are the most frequent source of contentiousness provoked by attempts to exercise the disability rights established by Sections 503 and 504. For instance, in Southeastern Community College v. Davis (1979), the Supreme Court refused to order that assessment of the plaintiff's application to a nursing program be based solely on academic record, as applicants' were. On the ground that her deafness prevented her from fully practicing the profession "safely" (for instance, she could not be a surgical nurse because her colleagues' surgical masks would prevent her from reading their lips), the Court decided that the public benefits of denying her this opportunity outweighed the personal benefits to Davis of being admitted. Litigation under the ADA commonly turns on questions of classification rather than access. Most of the ADA cases heard by the Supreme Court involve this issue. (Four have concerned whether specific physical conditions meet the ADA's classificatory criterion for being protected from disability discrimination, another addressed inconsistencies in how different statutes define disability, and yet another turned on whether disability is a classification that qualifies for Fourteenth Amendment protection.) (Francis and Silvers, 2000) For example, in Kirkingburg, the Court did not address the justice of denying the plaintiff employment as a driver, simply because of his monocular vision and despite his demonstrating adequate depth perception and a flawless driving record. Instead, the fact that the plaintiff had overcome the usual limitation of monocular vision and had passed the tests for depth perception meant, to the Court, that he could not be classified as disabled and so had no standing under the ADA.(Kirkingburg, 1999) Notice that, by pursuing individualized inquiries into whether plaintiffs' impairments are sufficiently limiting so that eligibility criteria are met, the Court has applied procedures characteristically applied in disputes about social welfare rights to adjudicate civil rights complaints. In sum, U.S. disability policy encompasses incongruous understandings of disabled people's rights. Even where civil rights and benefit entitlement statutes require the same compliance - for instance, the provision of a sign language interpreter for a person who cannot hear - the two kinds of laws supply quite disparate warrants for the same requirement. The ADA underwrites disabled people's equal right to the same degree of social participation enjoyed by other people. On the other hand, the Rehabilitation Act establishes disabled people's special right to the fulfillment of needs not experienced by other people. Disputes under the Rehabilitation Act focus on whether the actions required to provide disabled individuals with access are too burdensome on nondisabled people. Disputes under the ADA have, so far, assumed that such actions are required and have focused, instead, on who is included in the group for whom they must be executed. Disability policy in other nations exhibits similar complexity. For instance, neither Australia's 1992 Disability Discrimination Act(Jones and Marks, 2000), nor Section 15 of the Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms (enacted as the Canada Act in 1982) (Bickenbach, 2000), nor the UK's 1995 Disability Discrimination Act (Silvers, 1995; Corker, 2000) makes clear whether captioning, ramping, and print enlarging should be thought of in general terms - as integral elements of an increasingly inclusive social climate in which the existence of deaf, vision impaired, and mobility limited people, and their right to equal access to the world, are acknowledged. Or whether, on the other hand, these accommodations should be understood in particular terms - as contingent responses to the petitions of singular individuals with extraordinary needs. 2. 4. Are Disability Rights Redundant? Moral theories that center on justice typically foreground the goals of securing equality for all alike through the exercise of rights that all should recognize. There are, however, challenging reasons for thinking that assigning justice the preeminent moral role in ameliorating the disability problem disregards the realities of disability and especially of the dependency associated with it. Looked at in this light, grounding disability policy in other, more appropriate values should make appeals to disability rights subsidiary or even redundant. Writing about her relation with her disabled daughter, Eva Feder Kittay considers how we can best care for people made vulnerable by significant impairments. We should recognize that their lives have a value unrelated to productivity and profit: their contribution is the bonding that relationships of dependency create. This is an important contribution because the coherence of our sense of ourselves as persons relies on our relations with others. Supporting the bonding between seriously disabled individuals and their families helps realize the human capacity for moral connectedness. (Kittay, 1996, 2000) Relating to disabled people holds further beneficial lessons. The more we stress the importance of independence, Kittay observes, the more we are inclined to feel threatened by disabled people who remind us of our own potential for dependency. We should utilize this reminder to recognize that each of us has periods in which we need to be cared for and thus are susceptible to exploitation and abuse. Then we will not be motivated by the fantasy that our lives are at all moments under our own control. Susan Wendell also thinks feminist ethics that value care over justice, and interdependence over autonomy, afford disabled people a role preferable to the one they must assume under the traditional ethical standards of justice, equality, and autonomy. Within the embrace of an ethics of care, Wendell urges, disabled people would be free to acknowledge their limitations, dependencies, and other real differences. Unfortunately, cultural taboos rooted in the currently predominant value of self- determination through self-sufficiency now discourage disabled people from being honest in communicating their experiences. (Wendell, 1996) Far less optimistic about reforming cultural values than Kittay is, Wendell doubts that we will cease to occlude disability. She thinks fears of loosing bodily control and suffering are too deeply embedded in our culture to be dislodged. On the other hand, Alasdair MacIntyre casts the disabled as the quintessential moral insiders because rational consideration of their experience stimulates both personal and social virtue. (MacIntyre, 1999) Acknowledgement of disability plays an important role in answering the question 'Why be moral?", MacIntyre argues. The pervasiveness of human disability is a compelling reason for virtuous social conduct. Disability makes dependence an ineluctable element of human existence, and the disabled should not be relegated to the social fringe because their state is a condition we all have the potential to share. For MacIntyre, the occlusion of disability of which Wendell complains is indicative of an irrationally driven, scarcely virtuous culture. Personal and social virtues of acknowledged dependence facilitate our flourishing as dependent animals, he thinks. Further, laws that protect the disabled will prove hollow in societies where the virtues of acknowledged dependence are not cultivated.(MacIntyre, 2000) In societies where this is not so, even generally benevolent people "will tend to see the cause of the disabled as something competing with other causes ... They will not take the possibility of ... a career as a provider of care for the disabled as having any great claim upon them and they will not understand the importance of ... enhancing the status ... enjoyed by those who give their lives to such caregiving. Moreover, they will not recognize what important indicators these are of the moral wellbeing ... of their society."(MacIntyre, 2000: 85) This suggests that there may be an inverse ratio between a society's virtue and the need for its disabled citizens to invoke disability rights. 3. Conclusion Prior to calling attention to the urgency of recognizing disabled people's right to be in the world, Jacobus tenBroek studied and wrote about the reasons Americans of African descent should not be collectively enslaved, Americans of Japanese descent should not be collectively imprisoned, and women should not be collectively prohibited by statute from rewarding kinds of employment. (Tussman and tenBroek, 1949) It is no accident, then, to find him gripped by the similarities between such constraints upon the liberties of other minorities and disabled people's deprivation of social access. Nor is his supposition that all such wrongs are susceptible to similar remedies surprising. Whether his assumption in this regard is accurate remains an unresolved issue for both public policy and practical ethics. TenBroek's proposal emerged in a climate in which a tradition of casting welfare, rather than liberatory, values as the basis of disability rights prevailed. An even older tradition, in which virtue rather than duty properly motivates interactions with disabled people, also retained influence. In such tangled circumstances, which persist today, shapers of disability policy are inclined to elide competing theories of moral value and therefore to conflate the kinds of ethical appeals they made. One challenge for practical ethics, then, is to clarify the implications not only of various construals of disability rights, but also of theories on which the pursuit of certain goods, or the cultivation of certain virtues, eclipses proposals to address the social exclusion of disabled people through recognition of their rights. Equally important is the challenge of elevating both private and public efforts to address the disability problem by introducing into these exceedingly emotional and politicized debates the higher standards of lucidity, coherence, and sensitivity to nuances, associated with serious endeavors of practical ethics. Bibliography Albertsons, Inc. v. Kirkingburg, 1999 U.S. LEXIS 4369, *18 (June 22, 1999) Americans With Disabilities Act. 1990. PUBLIC LAW 101-336 JULY 26, 1990 104 STAT. 327st Cong., 101st sess. Amundson, Ron. 2000a. Against Normal Function. Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences. 31. 33-53 Amundson, Ron. 2000b. Biological Normality and the ADA. in Franc es, Leslie and Silvers, Anita. Americans with Disabilities: Implications of the Law for Individuals and Institutions. New York: Routledge. 102-110. Anderson, Elizabeth. 1999. What is the Point of Equality? Ethics 109. 287-337. Arneson, Richard. 2000. Disability, Priority and Social Justice. in Frances, Leslie and Silvers, Anita. Americans with Disabilities: Implications of the Law for Individuals and Institutions. New York: Routledge. 18-33. Baughn, Bill, Degener, Theresia, and Wolbring, Gregor. 2000. E- mails 1/11/2000, 1/12/2000, 1/18/2000. On file with the author. Baynton, Douglas, 1996. Forbidden Signs: American Culture and the Campaign Against Sign Language. Chicago, IL: University of Chica go Press Becker, Lawrence. 2000. The Good of Agency. in Frances, Leslie, and Silvers, Anita. Americans with Disabilities: Implications of the Law for Individuals and Institutions. New York: Routledge. 54-63 Bickenbach, Jerome. 1993. Physical Disability and Social Policy. Toronto: University of Toronto Press. Bickenbach, Jerome. 2000. The ADA v. the Canadian Charter of Rights: Disability Rights and the Social Model of Disability. in Frances, Leslie and Silvers, Anita. Americans with Disabilities: Implications of the Law for Individuals and Institutions. New York: Routledge. 342-356. Bragdon v. Abbott, 524 U.S. 624 (1998) Brock, Dan. 1994. The Human Genome Project and Human Identity." In Genes and Human Self-Knowledge: Historical and Philosophical Reflections on Modern Genetics, ed. Robert Weir, Susan Lawrence and Evan Fales. Ames, IO: University of Iowa Press, 1994: 18-33. Brock, Dan. 1995. Justice and the ADA: Does Prioritizing and Rationing Health Care Discriminate Against the Disabled?" Social Philosophy and Policy 12. 159-85. Brock, Dan. 2000. Health Care, Resource Prioritization and Dis crimination Against Persons with Disabilities. in Frances, Leslie and Silvers, Anita. Americans with Disabilities: Implications of the Law for Individuals and Institutions. New York: Routledge. 223-235. Buchanan, Allen. 1995. Equal Opportunity and Genetic Interven tion. Social Philosophy and Policy 12. 105-35. Buchanan, Allen. 1996. Choosing Who Will Be Disabled: Genetic Intervention and the Morality of Inclusion. Social Philosophy and Policy 13 Buck v. Bell, 1927. 274 U.S. 200. Burgdorf, Robert L. 1991. The Americans with Disabilities Act: Analysis and Implications of a Second-Generation Civil Rights Statute. Harvard Civil Rights-Civil Liberties Law Review. 418-419 Carlson, Angela Licia, 1998. Mindful Subjects: Classification and Cognitive Disability. A dissertation submitted in partial ful fillment of the requirements for the doctorate in philosophy, Toronto: University of Toronto. Cleveland v. Policy Management Systems Corp., 119 S.Ct. 1597 (1999) Corker, Mairian. The UK Disability Discrimination Act: Disabling Language, Justifying Inequitable Social Participation. in Franc es, Leslie and Silvers, Anita. Americans with Disabilities: Implications of the Law for Individuals and Institutions. New York: Routledge. 357-377. Daniels, Norman. 1987. Justice and Health Care. In Health Care Ethics: An Introduction, ed. Donald Van DeVeer and Tom Regan. Philadelphia, PA: Temple University Press. 290-325. Davis, Dena, 1997. Genetic Dilemmas and the Child's Right to an Open Future. The Hastings Center Report. 27, 7-14. Dworkin, Ronald. 1994. Will Clinton's Plan Be Fair? The New York Review of Books. January 13. 20-25. Baughn, Bill E-mails, Bill Baughn, Theresia Degener, Gregory Wolbring. 1/11/2000, 1/12/2000, 1/18/2000. On file with the author. Francis, Leslie and Silvers, Anita (ed.). 2000. Americans With Disabilities: Exploring Implications of the Law for Individuals and Institutions. New York: Routledge. Fuhrer, Marcus. 2000. Subjectifying Quality of Life as a Medical Rehabilitation Outcome. Disability and Rehabilitation. v 22, N. 11. 481-489. Funk, Robert, 1987. Disability Rights: From Caste to Class in the Context of Civil Rights in Gartner, A. and Joe, T. (ed.) in Images of the Disabled, Disabling Images, New York, NY: Praeger, 7-30. Gewirth, Alan. 1992. Rights in Becker, L and Becker, C. (ed.) in The Encyclopedia of Ethics. New York, Garland, 1103-1109. Hahn, Harlan. 2000. Disputing the Doctrine of Benign Neglect: A Challenge to the Disparate Treatment of Americans with Disabili ties. in Frances, Leslie and Silvers, Anita. Americans with Disabilities: Implications of the Law for Individuals and Insti tutions. New York: Routledge. 269-274. Hull, Richard. 1998. Defining Disability - A Philosophical Approach. Res Publica. IV. 199-210 Illingworth, Patricia and Parmet, Wendy. 2000. Positively Disabled: The Relationship Between the Definition of Disability and Rights Under the ADA. in Francis, Leslie and Silvers, Anita. Americans with Disabilities: Implications of the Law for Individuals and Institutions. New York: Routledge, 3-17. Jones, Melinda and Marks, Lee Ann. 2000. A Bright New Era of Equality, Independence, and Freedom - Casting an Australian Gaze on the ADA. in Frances, Leslie and Silvers, Anita. Americans with Disabilities: Implications of the Law for Individuals and Insti tutions. New York: Routledge. 371-386. Kass, Leon. 1983. Implications of the Human Right to Life". in Munson, Ronald. Intervention and Reflection: Basic Issues in Medical Ethics. Belmont: Wadsworth. Kevles, Daniel. 1998. Grounds for breeding: The amazing persist ence of eugenics in Europe and North America. Times Literary Supplement. 4944, 3-4 Kittay, Eva Feder, 1998. Love's Labor: Essays on Women, Equality, and Dependency. New York: Routledge. Kittay, Eva Feder. 2000. At Home with My Daughter: Reflections on Olmstead v. L.C. in Frances, Leslie and Silvers, Anita. Americans with Disabilities: Implications of the Law for Individuals and Institutions. New York: Routledge. 64-80. MacIntyre, Alasdair. 1999. Dependent Rational Animals: Why Human Beings Need the Virtues. Chicago: Open Court, MacIntyre, Alasdair. 2000. The Need for a Standard of Care. in Frances, Leslie and Silvers, Anita. Americans with Disabilities: Implications of the Law for Individuals and Institutions. New York: Routledge. 81-86. Magee, Bryan and Milligan, Martin. 1995. On Blindness. Oxford: Oxford University Press Milani, Adam. 1999. Living In The World: A New Look At The Disa bled in the Law of Torts. Catholic University Law Review . 48. Murphy v. United Parcel Service, Inc., 1999U.S. LEXIS 4370 (June 22, 1999) Murray, Christopher and Lopez, Allan. 1996. The Global Burden of Disease, Cambridge: Harvard School of Health. Olmstead v. L.C., 1999 U.S. LEXIS 4368 (June 22, 1999) Rosenberg, Alexander. 1986. "The Political Philosophy of Biologi cal Endowments, Social Philosophy and Policy, 5 2-31. Sen, Amartya K. 1980. Equality of What?" In McMurrin, S. (ed.), Tanner Lectures on Human Values, ed. S. McMurrin. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. Sen, Amartya K. 1992. Inequality Reexamined. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Sen, Amartya K., 1993. Capability and Well-Being. In Quality of Life, Nussbaum, Martha and Sen, Amartya K.(ed). Oxford, UK: Clarendon Press. Silvers, Anita. 1995. Reconciling Equality To Difference: Caring (F)or Justice For People With Disabilities. Hypatia. 10. 30-55, Silvers, Anita. 1997. Disability Rights, in Chadwick, Ruth (ed.). The Encyclopedia of Applied Ethics, I. San Diego: Academic Press, Inc., Vol. I, 781-796. Silvers, Anita: 1998, On Not Iterating Women's Disabilities: A Crossover Perspective on Genetic Dilemmas, in Donchin, Anne and Laura Purdy, (eds), Embodying Bioethics: Feminist Advances. Lanham, Maryland: Rowman & Littlefield, 177-202 Silvers, Anita. 2000. The Unprotected: Constructing Disability in the Context of Anti-Discrimination Law. in Frances, Leslie and Silvers, Anita. Americans with Disabilities: Implications of the Law for Individuals and Institutions. New York: Routledge. 126- 145. Silvers, Anita. 2001. "Bedside Justice: Personalizing Justice, Preserving Impartiality" in Rhodes, Rosamond, Battin, Margaret, and Silvers, Anita (ed.) Health Care and Social Justice. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Silvers, Anita, Wasserman, David and Mahowald, Mary. 1998a. Disability, Difference, Discrimination: Perspectives on Justice in Bioethics and Public Policy. Lanham, Maryland: Rowman and Littlefield Sober, Eliot. 1980. Evolution, Population Thinking, and Essentialism. Philosophy of Science, 47. 350-383. Stiker, Henri-Jacques, 1982. Corps infirmes et societies. Paris, FR: Aubier Montage, Southeastern Community College v. Davis. 1979. 442 U.S. 397 (1979) Sutton v. United Air Lines, Inc., 1999 U.S. LEXIS 4371 (June 22, 1999). TenBroek, Jacobus. 1966. The Right to Live in the World: The Disabled in the Law of Torts. California Law Review. 54. 841- 919. Trent, James, 1994. Inventing the Feeble Mind: A History of Mental Retardation in the United States. Berkeley, CA: University of California Press. Tussman, Joseph and tenBroek, Jacobus. 1949. The Equal Protection of the Laws, California Law Review, 37. Wendell, Susan. 1996. The Rejected Body: Feminist Philosophical Reflections on Disability. New York: Routledge Wolff, Jonathan. 2000. Disability in a Society of Equals, unpub lished ms. London: University College. Young, Iris Marion. 1990. Justice and the Politics of Difference. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. Young, Iris Marion, 1997. Asymmetrical Reciprocity: On Moral Respect, Wonder, and Enlarged Thought. Constellations 3 Young, Iris Marion. 2000. Disability and the Definition of Work. in Frances, Leslie and Silvers, Anita. Americans with Disabili ties: Implications of the Law for Individuals and Institutions. New York: Routledge. 169-173.